Front Back
True
According to Douglass Soccio, one general rule in philosophy is that philosophical questions cannot be settled by the empirical sciences or by appeals to religious faith or personal conviction.
False
According to Douglass Soccio, philosophy classes almost never focus on extended arguments.
False
According to Douglass Soccio, philosophy instructors want to help students obtain philosophical understanding and expect them to “solve” or “settle” great philosophical issues.
True
According to Douglass Soccio, philosophy has been characterized as the art of questioning.
False
All philosophy in the world began in Ancient Greece.
False
The word ‘philosophy’ is derived from the Latin words ‘philo’ and ‘sophia.’
True
Ontology is concerned with being and existence, and is a part of metaphysics.
False
Logic and epistemology are totally indistinguishable.
False
Philosophers of science are concerned with questions like “what causes cancer?”
True
Epistemology is concerned with theories of knowledge.
True
Philosophy pursues questions in every dimension of human life, and its techniques apply to problems in any field of study or endeavor.
False
Philosophy cannot examine concepts and views drawn from science, art, religion, politics, or any other realm.
False
No area of philosophy is concerned with the meanings of moral concepts like right action and obligation, and with formulating principles to guide moral decisions.
True
The title of the highest degree granted in most scholarly and scientific disciplines—“Doctor of Philosophy”—is evidence that philosophy once embraced nearly all forms of inquiry
True
The study of philosophy serves to develop intellectual abilities important for life as a whole, beyond the knowledge and skills required for any particular profession.
True
Shedding light on an accepted fact is not the aim of an argument.
True
‘Since’ and ‘because’ are indicator words for a premise.
False
A warning is a non-argument
False
The following is not a valid argument: P1: All human beings require H20 to live P2: Quigley is a human being ------------------------------------------------- C: Quigley requires H20 to live
True
The following is not a cogent argument: P1: Most human beings are marsupials P2: Artimus is a human being ---------------------------------------------- C: Artimus is a marsupial
True
Arguments cannot be either true or false.
True
The conclusion is the statement in an argument that the premises are claimed to support or imply.
False
Typical kinds of arguments includes warnings, reports, explanations and conditional statements.
False
Deductive arguments are never valid when it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false.
False
A valid deductive argument that has true premises is unsound.
True
Inductive arguments only claim that it is improbable that the premises be true and the conclusion false.
False
Cogent arguments are always deductive arguments.
False
The following argument is invalid: P1: Rawls thinks that justice necessarily adheres to the Difference Principle P2: The Difference Principle is an egalitarian principle --------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- C: Rawls thinks that jus…
False
All arguments that contain fallacies are good arguments.
False
No fallacies involve a mistake in reasoning.
True
Formal fallacies are found only in deductive arguments that have identifiable forms.
False
All valid arguments are fallacious.
True
Informal fallacies cannot be detected through mere inspection of the form or structure of an argument.
True
In an Appeal to Pity the support provided is not relevant to the argument’s conclusion.
False
When an argument “begs the question,” it means that the argument provides adequate premises that give adequate support for its conclusion.
True
Ethics, or moral philosophy, is the branch of philosophy that is concerned with conduct and character.
False
Moral philosophy is not concerned with the question of what makes right actions right.
False
Ethical theories try to elucidate the distinction between the existence and non-existence of material objects.
False
Moral philosophy is concerned with distinguishing between actions that are praiseworthy and those that are blameworthy.
True
Distinguishing between good and evil is not a concern of moral philosophy.
False
An ethical theory need only be clear to be appropriately characterized as a good ethical theory.
True
Good ethical theories provide enlightenment, i.e., they provide guidance for solving moral problems.
True
The question of whether we can ever know the difference between right and wrong is a good example of an interconnection between ethics and epistemology.
False
It is impossible to distinguish between ethics and axiology.
True
Supererogatory acts are always morally permissible.
False
Axiology is another name for economics.
True
Morally permissible acts are not morally wrong.
True
Currency is extrinsically valuable.
False
Doing the wrong thing is always supererogatory.
False
The aim of normative ethics is descriptive.
True
A normative ethical rule may also be prudential.
False
Metaethics always aims to be normative.
True
Metaethics is the analytical study of the discipline of ethics itself.
True
The is/ought problem raises the question of distinguishing between moral judgments and statements of fact.
False
Moral skepticism is the same thing as moral diversity.
True
Moral skepticism is an uncontroversial empirical fact.
True
Ethical relativism denies that there are absolutes in ethics.
True
Ethical relativists tend to reject the is/ought distinction.
False
Cultural relativism holds that, at the most, there are ethical truths relative to an individual believer.
False
Kant’s aim in the Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals is to establish several important moral principles.
True
Kant thinks that pure philosophy sets forth doctrines depending entirely on a priori principles.
True
For Kant, the laws of freedom are those laws in accordance with which everything ought to happen.
False
Kant’s idea of a metaphysics of morals is not the pure part of ethics.
False
According to Kant, all wills are good wills.
False
The good will is extrinsically valuable.
True
The good will is not the same as altruism.
False
Unlike securing one’s own happiness, manifesting a will good in itself is a conditioned good.
True
A perfectly good will always acts in accordance with duty.
False
The reason Kant thinks moral commands are unnecessary for divine wills is because divine wills are so powerful.
True
It is possible to act from self-interest and at the same time act in accordance with duty.
True
The moral worth of an action is not dependant upon the purpose that is to be attained by it.
False
An action can be done from duty only when the object of the action is realized.
True
All morally good acts are morally right.
False
All morally right acts are morally good.
True
Respect for the (moral) law includes doing one’s duty.
False
Inclination has nothing to do with desire.
False
Inclination always indicates something necessary, e.g., H2O.
False
A maxim is never a subjective rule.
True
We always act on maxims.
True
Ideally, our maxims can act as practical laws.
False
Practical laws are always prudential.
True
Unlike prudence, morality is “other-regarding.”
True
We should never act on maxims that should not become universal laws.
False .
Kant derives the supreme moral principle from examples of morality and popular moral positions.
True
Pure philosophy does not reject a priori reasoning in favor of a posteriori reasoning.
True
The reason the will is practical reason is because the derivation of actions from laws requires reason.
False
A divine will is imperfectly rational.
True
Hypothetical imperatives are addressed to imperfectly rational beings.
True
A hypothetical imperative which represents the practical necessity of an action as means for the promotion of happiness is assertoric.
False
Hypothetical imperatives hold as apodictic practical principles.
True
Hypothetical imperatives can hold as assertoric practical principles.
True
In an analytic proposition, the concept of willing the necessary action is contained within the concept of willing a presupposed end towards which we are inclined.
False
The CI is not a synthetic a priori proposition.
True
Imperatives of skill are hypothetical/analytic.
False
When a contradiction in will results from the application of the CI to a personal maxim, a contradiction in conception always follows.
False
All maxims are moral laws.
True
The 2nd formulation of the CI is less abstract than the 1st.
False
Like Kant, Hume believes that a moral principle can by itself give an incentive and produce an interest which could be called purely moral.
True
Hume thinks that the controversy over the general foundation of morals is between reason and sentiment.
False
A specious argument is one in which a great deal of space is given for alternative points of view.
False
Hume thinks that as long as our understanding stays cool, we will probably do the right thing.
True
Part of the telos of moral speculation is to help us get in the habit of doing the right thing.
True
According to Hume, proper reasoning is sufficient to give rise to the proper sentiment.
True
Reasoning is often necessary to give the sentiment a suitable influence on the mind.
False
Hume thinks that personal merit is a fundamental moral principle.
False
The qualities that should be ascribed to people are of no use to Hume’s inquiry into the principles of morals.
True
Claiming that the foundation of ethics is a question of fact, is a metaethical claim.
True
Kant disagreed with Hume as to the appropriate means to finding the fundamental principle(s) of morals.
True
Hume’s use of the experimental scientific method is also a naturalistic approach to ethics.
False
According to Hume, several qualities other than those which proceed from a tender sympathy with others and a generous concern for our species, are more entitled to the general good-will and approbation of humankind.
True
The merit of benevolence arises from its tendency to promote the interests of our species and bestow happiness on human society.
True
Utility is at least part of the merit of social virtues.
False
When making a moral judgment, utility is the last consideration.
False
The reason utility has nothing to do with questions concerning moral duty, is that Hume is not a deontologist.
True
Utility is not a virtue in both people and inanimate objects.
False
All moral affections or dislikes are not from education, and it follows from this that no moral affections or dislikes are from education.
True
Benevolence engages the affections of persons before any moral education occurs.
False
The end promoted by the social virtues is agreeable to us because of what we have been taught by society.
False
The end of social virtues is pleasing because it promotes self-interest.
False
Utility and self-love are nearly identical.
False
Utility alone accounts for the origin of morality.
True
Hume’s philosophy is appropriately thought of as a kind of naturalism because he relies on principles of human nature.
True
No one can be entirely indifferent to a well-represented passion, because everyone has the seeds and first principles of every passion.
True
A reductio is a deductive argument.
False
Assuming the opposite of the claim to be proven is not a part of arguing by reductio.
False
Reductio ad absurdum is a direct proof.
False
Previously established premises and axioms cannot be used in a reductio.
True
Kant was not an empiricist.
False
Hume’s moral philosophy is not an example of empiricism.
True
Claiming something about every moral theory constitutes a metaethical claim.
True
It is possible to reach a conclusion a priori from a principle that has already been proven a posteriori.
True
Happiness is the summum bonum.
False
All useful goods are goods in their own right.
True
Both animate and inanimate objects have functions.
False
Eudaimonia is complete with qualification.
True
Good fortune is not a sufficient condition for happiness.
False
The soul is an ontologically distinct entity from the body.
True
Both the rational and nonrational parts of the soul have a function.
True
Wisdom and prudence are not virtues of character.
False
Virtue of character is attained wholly a priori.
True
Virtue is intrinsically valuable.
True
The doctrine of the Mean applies to some ethical virtues.
False
Prudent people naturally know what happiness is.
True
Prudence is a necessary condition for full virtue.
False
Having the virtues of thought means that you can be moved to action by thought alone.
False
Akrasia is the combination of eudaimonia and virtuous action.
False
Being overcome by pleasure is a necessary condition for happiness.

Access the best Study Guides, Lecture Notes and Practice Exams

Login

Join to view and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or
We will never post anything without your permission.
Don't have an account?
Sign Up

Join to view 2 2 and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or

By creating an account you agree to our Privacy Policy and Terms Of Use

Already a member?