Unformatted text preview:

Economics 201B–Second HalfLecture 6, 4/1/10Revised 4/6/10, Revisions Marked by ** and StickyNotesThe Second Welfare Theorem in the Arrow DebreuEconomyTheorem 1 (Second Welfare Theorem) (Pure ExchangeCase) If x∗is Pareto Optimal in a pure exchange economy,with strongly monotone, continuous, convex preferences, thereexists a price vector p∗and an income transfer T such that(p∗,x∗,T) is a Walrasian Equilibrium with Transfers.Outline of Proof:• LetAi= {x i− x∗i: x iix∗i}A =Ii=1Ai= {a1+ ···+ aI: ai∈ Ai}Then 0 ∈ A (if it were, we’d have a Pareto improvement).• By Minkowski’s Theorem, find p∗=0suchthatinf p∗· A ≥ 0• Show RL+\{0}⊂ Aiand hence p∗≥ 0.• Show inf p∗· Ai=0foreachi.• Define T to make x∗iaffordable at p∗:Ti= p∗· x∗i− p∗· ωiShowIi=1Ti=0andx∗i∈ Qi(p∗,T)1• Use strong monotonicity to show that p∗ 0.• Showp∗ 0 ⇒ Qi(p∗,T)=Di(p∗,T)Now, for the details:• LetAi= {x i− x∗i: x iix∗i}A =Ii=1Ai= {a1+ ···+ aI: ai∈ Ai}Claim:0 ∈ AIf 0 ∈ A, there exists ai∈ Aisuch thatIi=1ai=0Letx i= x∗i+ aiSince x i− x∗i= ai∈ Ai,wehavex iix∗iIi=1x i=Ii=1(x∗i+ ai)=Ii=1x∗i+Ii=1ai=Ii=1x∗i=¯ωTherefore, x is an exact** allocation, x Pareto improves x∗,so x∗is not Pareto Optimal, contradiction. Therefore, 0 ∈ A.2•∃p∗=0inf p∗· A ≥ 0Aiis convex, so A is convex (easy exercise). By Minkowski’sTheorem, there exists p∗=0suchthat0=p∗· 0 ≤ inf p∗· A =Ii=1inf p∗· AiThe fact that inf p∗· A =Ii=1inf p∗· Aiis an exercise; onceyou figure out what you have to prove, it is obvious.• We claim that p∗≥ 0.Suppose not, so p∗ < 0forsome ,WLOGp∗1< 0. Letx i= x∗i+⎛⎜⎜⎝−1p∗1, 0,...,0⎞⎟⎟⎠By strong monotonicity, x iix∗i,so⎛⎜⎜⎝−1p∗1, 0,...,0⎞⎟⎟⎠∈ AiSoinf p∗· Ai≤ p∗·⎛⎜⎜⎝−1p∗1, 0,...,0⎞⎟⎟⎠= −1 < 0inf p∗· A =Ii=1inf p∗· Ai≤−I< 0a contradiction that shows p∗≥ 0.• We claim that inf p∗· Ai=0foreachi:Suppose ε>0. By strong monotonicity,x∗i+(ε,...,ε) ix∗i3so(ε,...,ε) ∈ Aisoinf p∗· Ai≤ p∗· (ε,...,ε)Since ε is an arbitrary positive number, inf p∗· Aiis less thanevery positive number, soinf p∗· Ai≤ 0SinceIi=1inf p∗· Ai≥ 0,inf p∗· Ai=0(i =1,...,I)• Define T to make x∗iaffordable at p∗. We claim that T is anincome transfer andx∗i∈ Qi(p∗,T)LetTi= p∗· x∗i− p∗· ωiIi=1Ti=Ii=1(p∗· x∗i− p∗· ωi)= p∗·⎛⎜⎝Ii=1x∗i−Ii=1ωi⎞⎟⎠= p∗· (¯ω − ¯ω)=0so T is an income transfer.p∗· x∗i= p∗· (ωi+(x∗i− ωi))= p∗· ωi+ p∗· (x∗i− ωi)= p∗· ωi+ Ti4sox∗i∈ Bi(p∗,T)If x iix∗i,thenx i− x∗i∈ Ai,sop∗· x i= p∗· (x∗i+(x i− x∗i))= p∗· x∗i+ p∗· (x i− x∗i)≥ p∗· x∗i+infp∗· Ai= p∗· x∗i= p∗· ωi+ Tisox∗i∈ Qi(p∗,T) ∗∗• Use strong monotonicity to show that p∗ 0.Lemma 2 If iis continuous and complete, and x iy,then there exists ε>0 such that(B(x, ε) ∩ Xi) iyProof: **If (B(x, ε) ∩ Xi)={x} for some ε>0, i.e. x isan isolated point in Xi, then the lemma is true, since x iy.If x is not an isolated point in Xi,thenwecanfindxn→ x,xn∈ Xi, xniy; by completeness, we have y ixnfor eachn.Sinceiis continuous, y ix,sox iy, a contradictionwhich proves the lemma.Since p∗≥ 0andp∗=0,p∗> 0; since in addition ¯ω  0,p∗· ¯ω>0, sop∗· ωi+ Ti> 0forsomeiIf p∗ =0forsome (WLOG = 1), letx i= x∗i+(1, 0,...,0)5By strong monotonicity, x iix∗i.p∗· x i= p∗· x∗i= p∗· ωi+ Ti> 0Find (WLOG = 2) such thatp∗ > 0,x 2i> 0Since x iix∗i,letε>0 be chosen to satisfy the conclusionof the Lemma. If necessary, we may make ε smaller to ensurethat ε ≤ 2x 2i.Letx i= x i− (0,ε/2, 0,...,0)Since Xi= RL+, x i∈ Xi, so by the Lemma, x iix∗i.Butp∗· x i<p· x i= p∗· ωi+ Ti, which shows that x∗i∈ Qi(p∗,T),a contradiction which proves that p∗ 0.• Showp∗ 0 ⇒ Qi(p∗,T)=Di(p∗,T)– Case 1: p∗· ωi+ Ti=0. Sincep∗ 0, Bi(p∗,T)={0},soQi(p∗,T)=Di(p∗,T)={0}– Case 2: p∗· ωi+ Ti> 0Suppose x ∈ Qi(p∗,T) but x ∈ Di(p∗,T). Then thereexists z ix such that z ∈ Bi(p∗,T), hence p∗· z ≤p∗· ωi+ Ti.Sincex ∈ Qi(p∗,T), p∗· z ≥ p∗· ωi+ Ti,sop∗· z = p∗· ωi+ Ti> 0By Lemma 2, there exists ε>0 such that|z − z| <ε,z ∈ RL+⇒ z  x6Letz = z⎛⎜⎜⎝1 −ε2|z|⎞⎟⎟⎠Since z ∈ RL+, z ∈ RL+.|z − z| =εz2|z|=ε2<εso z  x.p∗· z = p∗· z⎛⎜⎜⎝1 −ε2|z|⎞⎟⎟⎠=(p∗· ωi+ Ti)⎛⎜⎜⎝1 −ε2|z|⎞⎟⎟⎠<p∗· ωi+ Tiwhich contradicts the assumption that x ∈ Qi(p∗,T). Thisshows Qi(p∗,T) ⊂ Di(p∗,T); since clearly Di(p∗,T) ⊂Qi(p∗,T), Qi(p∗,T)=Di(p∗,T).What if preferences are not convex?• Second Welfare Theorem may fail if preferences are nonconvex.• Diagram gives an economy with two goods and two agents,and a Pareto optimum x∗so that so that the utility levels ofx∗cannot be approximated by a Walrasian Equilibrium withTransfers.• If p∗is the price which locally supports x∗,andT is the in-come transfer which makes x affordable with respect to theprices p∗, there is a unique Walrasian equilibrium with trans-fers (z∗,q∗,T); z∗is much more favorable to agent I and muchless favorable to agent II than x∗is.7• This is the worst that can happen under standard assumptionson preferences. Given a Pareto optimum x∗, there is a Wal-rasian quasiequilibrium with transfers (z∗,p∗,T) such that allbut L people are indifferent between x∗and z∗.ThoseL peo-ple are treated quite harshly (they get zero consumption). Onecould be less harsh and give these L people carefully chosenconsumption bundles in the convex hull of their quasidemandsets, but one would then have to forbid them from trading,a prohibition that would in practice be difficult to


View Full Document

Berkeley ECON 201B - Lecture Notes

Download Lecture Notes
Our administrator received your request to download this document. We will send you the file to your email shortly.
Loading Unlocking...
Login

Join to view Lecture Notes and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or
We will never post anything without your permission.
Don't have an account?
Sign Up

Join to view Lecture Notes 2 2 and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or

By creating an account you agree to our Privacy Policy and Terms Of Use

Already a member?