DOC PREVIEW
MIT 24 231 - Ayer’s Emotivism

This preview shows page 1 out of 4 pages.

Save
View full document
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 4 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 4 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience

Unformatted text preview:

24.231 Ethics – Handout 3 Ayer’s Emotivism Emotivism: Moral judgments are not truth-apt, but rather, are expressions of sentiments of approval or disapproval: e.g., saying “Murder is wrong” amounts to saying “Boo to murder!”: “[I]f I say to someone ‘You acted wrongly in stealing that money’, I am not stating anything more than if I had simply said, ‘You stole that money.’ In adding that this action is wrong, I am not making any further statement about it, I am simply evincing my moral disapproval about it. It is as if I had said, ‘You stole that money,’ in a peculiar tone of horror, or written with the addition of some special exclamation marks. The tone, or the exclamation marks, adds nothing to the literal meaning of the sentence. It merely serves to show that the expression of it is attended by certain feelings in the speaker. “If now I generalise my previous statement and say, ‘Stealing money is wrong,’ I produce a sentence which has no factual meaning – that is, expresses no proposition which can be either true or false. It is as if I had written ‘Stealing money!!’ – where the shape and thickness of the exclamation marks show, by a suitable convention, that a special sort of moral disapproval is the feeling which is being expressed.” (Ayer, “The Emotive Theory of Ethics,” p. 124) (c) Alfred Jules Ayer. All rights reserved. This content is excluded from our Creative Commons license. For more information, see http://ocw.mit.edu/fairuse. Ayer, A. J. "The Emotive Theory of Ethics." Chapter 10 in Moral Philosophy: Selected Readings. 2nd ed. Edited by George Sher. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt-Brace, 1996, pp. 120-128. ISBN: 9780155017559.Ayer’s argument for emotivism: (1) The Verification Principle: A synthetic proposition is meaningful, and hence can be true or false, only if it is empirically verifiable. All literally meaningful propositions are either analytic – true by definition – or else empirically verifiable. (bottom of p. 123) (2) Ethical statements cannot be translated into statements of empirical fact – that is, no natural reduction of ethical concepts is possible. (pp. 122-123) So they are not empirically verifiable. (3) Ethical statements are synthetic, not analytic – that is, they aren’t true by definition. (4) Non-cognitivism: Therefore (from 1, 2, and 3) ethical statements are not literally meaningful, and can be neither true nor false. Emotivism is one version of non-cognitivism – Ayer’s preferred version. According to emotivism, to make a moral judgment is to express an emotion. But there are other versions of non-cognitivism (the view that moral judgments are not truth-evaluable propositions), and some of these may avoid some of the worries raised by Ayer’s emotivism.1 1 Another prominent version of non-cognitivism is prescriptivism, according to which moral judgments are really commands, and “murder is wrong” should be understood as equivalent to “don’t murder!” (R.M. Hare was a leadig prescriptivist.) More recent non-cognitivists, calling themselves quasi-realists, have tried to develop versions of the view that explain why we are entitled to act as if our moral judgments are truth-apt despite the fact they strictly-speaking aren’t (leading quasi-realists are Simon Blackburn and Allan Gibbard). 1Evaluating Ayer’s argument: (1) We might question the Verification Principle. Is it true that only analytic or empirically verifiable statements are meaningful or truth-apt? • It seems like we can think of some synthetic propositions that seem both truth-apt and not empirically verifiable: e.g., there are some species that will never be discovered; Caesar sneezed at noon on the 1st day of the 1st month of 50 B.C. • Mathematical statements might be both synthetic (not true in virtue of meaning) and non-empirical • Some philosophers (notably Quine) have called into question the legitimacy of the analytic-synthetic distinction on which the principle relies • If we accept that ethical statements are not literally meaningful because they are synthetic and not empirically verifiable, then we’ll also have to judge a lot of other statements as not meaningful or truth-apt: e.g., every event has a cause, or the future will behave like the past… • The Verification Principle itself seems to be synthetic but not empirically verifiable. So should we conclude that it is meaningless and not truth-apt? • We might think Ayer assumes to quickly that because we can’t empirically verify ethical statements, and because moral intuitions disagree, there is no reasoned way of disputing about ethics. (2) Ayer argues against the possibility of naturalistic reductions of ethical concepts by arguing against a few influential attempts at such reductions: two versions of subjectivism and one version of utilitarianism. • He argues that any attempt to reduce normative concepts like “right” to natural ones like “generally approved of” or “approved of by me” or “pleasure-maximizing” fails because is wrongly implies that someone who acknowledges that an act has the natural property in question but denies it has the normative property is contradicting himself. Ayer says that while someone who says “I approve of that, but it’s not right” or “That’s pleasant, but it’s not good” may be making a mistaken moral judgment, he is not contradicting himself, as the subjectivist or the utilitarian would have to say.2 • It’s important to recognize the difference between subjectivism and Ayer’s emotivism: subjectivism might translate “Murder is wrong” as “I disapprove of murder; this is a truth-evaluable statement. Emotivism translates “Murder is wrong” as an emotive expression of the disapproval itself: e.g., “Boo for 2 Ayer is here taking utilitarianism to be a naturalistic meta-ethical theory offering a reductive account of what our moral terms mean: e.g., “right” means “happiness-maximizing”. But many defenders of utilitarianism defend it not as an account of what our moral terms mean, but rather as a first-order account of what makes actions right; such utilitarians needn’t think that “right” means “happiness-maximizing” – rather, they think that all and only those actions that maximize happiness have the (separate) property of being right. 23murder!” ; the statement doesn’t express a proposition


View Full Document

MIT 24 231 - Ayer’s Emotivism

Download Ayer’s Emotivism
Our administrator received your request to download this document. We will send you the file to your email shortly.
Loading Unlocking...
Login

Join to view Ayer’s Emotivism and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or
We will never post anything without your permission.
Don't have an account?
Sign Up

Join to view Ayer’s Emotivism 2 2 and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or

By creating an account you agree to our Privacy Policy and Terms Of Use

Already a member?