DOC PREVIEW
Topologies on Types

This preview shows page 1-2-3-27-28-29 out of 29 pages.

Save
View full document
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 29 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 29 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 29 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 29 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 29 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 29 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 29 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience

Unformatted text preview:

Topologies on TypesEddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen MorrisTalk for Southwestern Economic Theory ConferenceArizona State UniversityMarch 2006Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesMotivation Harsanyi (1967/68), Mertens and Zamir (1985): single "universal typespace" incorporates all incomplete information Economic researchers work with small type spaces: leap of faith thatthese capture avor of universal type space1Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types"Finite types" dense in universal type space under product topology, but But strategic outcomes not continuous with respect to product topology Finite common prior types are dense in product topology (Lipman 2003) Types with unique rationalizable outcomes are open and dense in theproduct topology (Yildiz 2006)2Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesDening a Strategic TopologyTWO TYPES ARE CLOSE IF THEIR STRATEGIC BEHAVIOR IS SIMILARIN ALL STRATEGIC SITUATIONS1. "Strategic situations": Fix space of uncertainty  and all possible beliefsand higher order beliefs about . Vary nite action sets and payofunctions depending on actions and .2. "Strategic behavior": interim (correlated) rationalizable actions, i.e.,those actions consistent with common knowledge of rationality.3. "Similar" strategic behavior: Allow "-rationality3Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesResults MAIN RESULT: Finite types are dense in the strategic topology{ nite common prior types are NOT dense in the strategic topology{ open sets of types have multiple rationalizable outcomes Product topology implies upper hemicontinuity of rationalizable outcomes Lower strategic convergence implies upper strategic convergence and isstrictly stronger than the product topology Finite types are nonetheless "non-generic" (category 1) in both productand strategic topology4Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesElectronic Mail Game two players 1 and 2 two actions N and I two payo states 0 and 1 payos: = 0 N IN 0; 0 0; 2I 2; 0 2; 2 = 1 N IN 0; 0 0; 2I 2; 0 1; 15Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types with probability , it is common knowledge that  = 1 otherwise{  = 1 with probability { player 1 only informed if  is 0 or 1{ if  = 1, player 1 sends a message to player 2, message lost withprobability { if player 2 receives a conrmation, he sends a reply - lost withprobability .... write t11for the type of player i for whom  is common knowledge write tikfor the type of player i for whom  is not common knowledgebut he has sent k  1 messages{ for type t1k, 1 knows that 2 knows that (k  2 times)::: = 16Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types{ for type t2k, 2 knows that [1 knows that 2 knows that ( k  2times)::: = 1] Thus Ti= fti1; ti2; ::::g [ fti1g. Common Prior = 0 t21t22t23t24   t21t11(1  )  0 0 0    0t120 0 0 0    0t130 0 0 0    0t140 0 0 0    0.....................t110 0 0 0    07Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types = 1 t21t22         t21t110 0          0t12(1  )  (1  ) (1  )  (1  )2         0t130 (1  )  (1  )3      0...............   0.....................t110 0 0 0     t1k! t11in product topology8Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types Iterative argument establishes that N is the only "-rationalizable actionfor type tikfor any " <1+2and k < 1{ N is only rationalizable action for type t11{ type t21assigns probability1+2to type t11; thus payo to invest is atmost1  2  (1) +12  (2) = 1 + 2  < 12{ type t12asigns probability1+2to type t21.... Both N and I are rationalizable for type ti1. Thus example shows failure of lower hemicontinuity w.r.t. producttopology No failure of upper hemicontinuity w.r.t. product topology9Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types However, ti1is itself a nite type, so this example does not show afailure of denseness10Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesTypes two players, 1 and 2 nite payo states  Type t = (1; 2; :::) 2 1k=0 (Xk) whereX0= X1= X0  (X0)Xk= Xk1  (Xk1) T is set of "coherent" types11Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types There exists homeomorphism  : T !  (T  ) we ignore "redundant types" - do not matter for our soln concept "nite types": belong to a nite belief closed subset of the universal typespace "product topology": tni! tiif ki(tni) ! ki(ti) as n ! 1 for all k{ where ki(ti) 2  (Xk1) is type ti's kth level beliefs{ often studied, but we do not expect continuous behavior12Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesGames A (two player) game G 2 G consists of{ nite action sets Ai{ payo functions gi: A   ! [M; M]13Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesInterim Rationalizability R0i(ti; G; ") = AiRk+1i(ti; G; ")=8>>>>>>><>>>>>>>:ai2 Ai9 2 T j   Ajsuch that(i) (tj; ; aj) : aj2 Rkj(tj; G; ") = 1(ii) margT  =  i(ti)(iii)R(tj;;aj)gi(ai; aj; )gi(a0i; aj; )d  "for all a0i2 Ai9>>>>>>>=>>>>>>>;14Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on Types Ri(ti; G; ") = \k1Rki(ti; G; ") Properties (see DFM "Interim Correlated Rationalizability"http://www.princeton.edu/~smorris/pdfs/interimrationalizability.pdf){ Doesn't depend on redundant types{ Ri(ti; G; ") is the set of actions that might be played in any "-equilibrium on any type space by a type whose higher order beliefs aregiven by ti{ Thus Ri(ti; G; ") is the set of actions consistent with commonknowledge of "-rationality for a type whose higher order beliefs aregiven by ti15Eddie Dekel, Drew Fudenberg and Stephen Morris Topologies on TypesConvergence Properties Let hi(tijai; G) be the "rationalizability"


Topologies on Types

Download Topologies on Types
Our administrator received your request to download this document. We will send you the file to your email shortly.
Loading Unlocking...
Login

Join to view Topologies on Types and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or
We will never post anything without your permission.
Don't have an account?
Sign Up

Join to view Topologies on Types 2 2 and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or

By creating an account you agree to our Privacy Policy and Terms Of Use

Already a member?