DOC PREVIEW
MIT 24 231 - Lecture Notes

This preview shows page 1-2 out of 5 pages.

Save
View full document
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 5 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 5 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 5 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience

Unformatted text preview:

124.231 Ethics – Handout 22 Susan Wolf, “Moral Saints” (1) What makes a moral saint? Is it what we do? Or what motivates us? Or what our character is like? The difference is important – there may be a disconnect between good motives and good actions, between good or virtuous character and the ability to perform good actions… Wolf defines a moral saint as “a person whose every action is as morally good as possible, a person, that is, who is as morally worthy as can be.” But the first clause is importantly different from the second. We might call the first person a “moral hero” and the second a “moral saint” (following Louis Pojman), to keep our ideas straight. Pojman: “A hero is one who accomplishes good deeds when the average person would be prevented by fear, terror, or a drive of self-interest. A saint is one who acts for good when inclination, desire, or self-interest would prevent most people from so acting.” - Admiral James B. Stockdale Lecture on Ethics and Leadership at the University of San Diego, April 13, 2000, “Moral Saints and Heroes” Sometimes, being a hero might require not being a saint (we can talk about examples). Wolf discusses two kinds of saints: The Loving Saint, perhaps characteristic of the utilitarian ideal, whose own well-being simply consists in the well-being of others; The Rational Saint, perhaps characteristic of the Kantian ideal, who retains some non-moral and even selfish desires, but, out of duty, does not act on them (except, I suppose, to the extent that morality permits doing so…) (2) Is Wolf right that moral saints are less attractive human beings than they could be? That they are boring, humorless, and no fun? Wolf: Moral saints are unattractive because: ‐ They lack the "ability to enjoy the enjoyable in life" ‐ They are so "very, very nice" that they have to be "dull-witted or humorless or bland" – we like Han Solo better than Luke Skywalker ‐ They have no time for literature, music, or sports and so live a life that seems "strangely barren" ‐ What is missing in the saint's life are the non-moral virtues: a robust sense of humor, a refined musical or artistic ability, culinary acuity, and athletic prowess (she allows that a saint may have some of these virtues – by accident – if, for example, she became a saint late in life, but saintliness allows no time and energy to develop these talents. 2‐ "The moral virtues, given that they are, by hypothesis, all present in the same individual, and to an extreme degree, are apt to crowd out the non-moral virtues, as well as many of the interests and personal characteristics that we generally think contribute to a healthy, well-rounded, richly developed character.” Does this seem right? Aren’t many of these qualities going to be very useful to a moral saint (especially a certain level of pragmatism and sense of humor!)? It’s true that a moral saint is unlike to be a musical virtuoso or a wine connoisseur, but there are other ways to be an attractive person. And sometimes developing ones talents can be a very good means towards making a different in the world – take, for example, Bill Gates. (3) Is it good or bad for us to be moral saints? Moral heroes? Eudaimonistic ethics, held by Aristotle and Plato among others, suggests that true happiness consists in being as morally perfect as possible. And it does seem that ‘loving your neighbor as yourself’ can protect you to some extent from suffering too much under your own burdens – it puts them in perspective. But Wolf worries that moral saints would lack some qualities necessary to develop the kind of life we think is good for the person who leads it – personal interests and projects and special relationships… Also, of course, a moral saint will often sacrifice her own well-being for the well-being of others – a definition of happiness that makes that impossible seems to be leaving something out. (4) Do plausible moral theories tell us not to be moral saints? Utilitarianism: Wolf says U would not support moral sainthood as a universal ideal, because a world peopled only by moral saints would be less good than it could be. But it remains possible that individual utilitarians should aim, in their own lives, at being as morally good as possible. ‐ Wolf is unconvinced, given the current state of the world, by the suggestion (found in Mill, for example) that we’d to best to promote the total happiness if we cared mainly for ourselves. ‐ It seems more plausible that we’d do better, by utilitarian standards, if we cared about some things non-instrumentally that on the utilitarian picture have only instrumental value. ‐ Wolf agrees that utilitarianism may leave the moral saint some limited room to develop her talents, etc., because she’ll be a more effective promoter of the good that way. ‐ But, says Wolf, even when U allows this, it gives the moral saint “one thought too many” (B. Williams). The utilitarian saint would value projects and talents and relationships only as means to or at best as constituents of happiness, and be willing to sacrifice them as soon as another project or relationship could produce more happiness. This “shallow appreciation” for such projects or talents or relationships brings the utilitarian saint to 3close to our common-sense picture of the saint from which Wolf began to escape her criticisms of that figure. Kantianism: whether the Kantian moral saint comes too close to the common-sense moral saint to be an attractive ideal depends, Wolf says, on our reading of Kantianism. ‐ On a reading of Kantianism that emphasizes the requirement to take up the ends of others as our own, and to perfect ourselves, the Kantian saint will also have too little room to develop her own talents, relationships, and projects, and will have “one thought too many.” ‐ On an alternate, minimalist reading of Kant, that emphasizes not violating certain rules in our interactions with others, much more room might be left for pursuing non-moral virtues. ‐ But, Wolf argues, a moral theory that in this way puts an upper bound on what morality demands fails to capture the thought that, e.g., Mother Theresa, even if less attractive (on Wolf’s view) than, say, Katherine Hepburn, is nonetheless more morally admirable. Need either the Kantian or the utilitarian saint have one thought too many? That


View Full Document

MIT 24 231 - Lecture Notes

Download Lecture Notes
Our administrator received your request to download this document. We will send you the file to your email shortly.
Loading Unlocking...
Login

Join to view Lecture Notes and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or
We will never post anything without your permission.
Don't have an account?
Sign Up

Join to view Lecture Notes 2 2 and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or

By creating an account you agree to our Privacy Policy and Terms Of Use

Already a member?