Unformatted text preview:

Attitudes Towards Risk 14.123 Microeconomic Theory III Muhamet Yildiz Model  C = R = wealth level  Lottery = cdf F (pdf f)  Utility function u : R→R  U(F) ≡ EF(u) ≡∫u(x)dF(x)  EF(x) ≡∫xdF(x) 1Attitudes Towards Risk DM is  risk averse if EF(u) ≤ u(EF(x)) (∀F)  strictly risk averse if EF(u)< u(EF(x)) (∀ “risky” F)  risk neutral if EF(u)= u(EF(x)) (∀F)  risk seeking if EF(u) ≥ u(EF(x)) (∀F) DM is  risk averse if u is concave  strictly risk averse if u is strictly concave  risk neutral if u is linear  risk seeking if u is convex Certainty Equivalence  CE(F) = u⁻¹(U(F))=u⁻¹(EF(u))  DM is  risk averse if CE(F) ≤ EF(x) for all F;  risk neutral if CE(F) = EF(x) for all F;  risk seeking if CE(F) ≥ EF(x) for all F.  Take DM1 and DM2 with u1 and u2.  DM1 is more risk averse than DM2  Ù u1 is more concave than u2,  Ù u1= φ◦ u2 for some concave function φ,  Ù CE1(F) ≡ u1⁻¹(EF(u1)) ≤ u2⁻¹(EF(u2)) ≡ CE2(F) 2Absolute Risk Aversion  absolute risk aversion: rA(x) = -u′′(x)/u′(x)  constant absolute risk aversion (CARA) u(x) =-e-αx  If x ~ N(μ,σ²), CE(F) = μ - ασ²/2  Fact: More risk aversion Ù higher absolute risk aversion everywhere  Fact: Decreasing absolute risk aversion (DARA) Ù ∀y>0, u2 with u2(x)≡u(x+y) is less risk averse Relative risk aversion:  relative risk aversion: rR(x) = -xu′′(x)/u′(x)  constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) u(x)=-x1-ρ/(1-ρ),  When ρ = 1, u(x) = log(x).  Fact: Decreasing relative risk aversion (DRRA) Ù ∀t>1, u2 with u2(x)≡u(tx) is less risk averse 3Application: Insurance  wealth w and a loss of $1 with probability p.  Insurance: pays $1 in case of loss costs q;  DM buys λ units of insurance.  Fact: If p = q (fair premium), then λ = 1 (full insurance). ■ Expected wealth w – p for all λ.  Fact: If DM1 buys full insurance, a more risk averse DM2 also buys full insurance.  CE2(λ) ≤ CE1(λ) ≤ CE1(1) = CE2(1). Application: Optimal Portfolio Choice  With initial wealth w, invest α ∈ [0,w] in a risky asset that pays a return z per each $ invested; z has cdf F on [0,∞).  U(α) = ∫0 ∞ u(w+αz-α) dF(z); concave  It is optimal to invest α > 0 iff E[z] > 1. ■ U’(0) = ∫0 ∞ u’(w)(z-1) dF(z) = u’(w)(E[z]-1).  If agent with utility u1 optimally invests α1, then an agent with more risk averse u2 (same w) optimallyinvests α2 ≤ α1.  DARA ⇒ optimal α increases in w.  CARA ⇒ optimal α is constant in w.  CRRA (DRRA) ⇒ optimal α/w is constant (increasing) 4Optimal Portfolio Choice – Proof  u2=g(u1); g is concave; g’(u1(w)) = 1.  Ui(α) ≡∫ui(w+α(z-1))(z-1) dF(z)  U2’(α)- U1’(α) = ∫[u2(w+α(z-1))- u1(w+α(z-1))](z-1)dF(z) ≤ 0.  g’(u1(w+α1z-α1)) < g’(u1(w)) = 1 Ù z > 1.  u2(w+α(z-1)) < u1(w+α(z-1)) Ù z > 1.  α2 ≤ α1 Stochastic Dominance  Goal: Compare lotteries with minimal assumptions on preferences  Assume that the support of all payoff distributions is bounded. Support = [a,b].  Two main concepts:  First-order Stochastic Dominance: A payoff distribution is preferred by all monotonic Expected Utility preferences.  Second-order Stochastic Dominance: A payoff distribution is preferred by all risk averse EU preferences. 5FSD  DEF: F first-order stochastically dominates G Ù F(x) ≤ G(x) for all x.  THM: F first-order stochastically dominates G Ù for every weakly increasing u: →, ∫u(x)dF(x) ≥∫u(x)dG(x). Proof:  “If:” for F(x*) > G(x*), define u = 1{x>x*}.  “Only if”: Assume F and G are strictly increasing and continuous on [a,b].  Define y(x) = F-1(G(x)); y(x) ≥ x for all x  ∫u(y)dF(y) = ∫u(y(x))dF(y(x)) = ∫u(y(x))dG(x) ≥∫u(x)dG(x) MPR and MLR Stochastic Orders  DEF: F dominates G in the Monotone ProbabilityRatio (MPR) sense if k(x) ≡ G(x)/F(x) is weaklydecreasing in x.  THM: MPR dominance implies FSD.  DEF: F dominates G in the Monotone Likelihood Ratio (MLR) sense if ℓ(x) ≡ G’(x)/F’(x) is weakly decreasing.  THM: MLR dominance implies MPR dominance. 6SSD  Assume: F and G has the same mean  DEF: F second-order stochastically dominates G Ù for every non-decreasing concave u, ∫u(x)dF(x) ≥∫u(x)dG(x).  DEF: G is a mean-preserving spread of F Ù y = x + ε for some x ~ F, y ~ G, and ε with E[ε|x] = 0.  THM: The following are equivalent:  F second-order stochastically dominates G.  G is a mean-preserving spread of F .  ∀t ≥ 0, ∫0 tG(x)dx ≥∫0 tF(x)dx. SSD  Example: G (dotted) is a mean-preservingspread of F (solid). 1 x0 b FG 7MIT OpenCourseWarehttp://ocw.mit.edu 14.123 Microeconomic Theory III Spring 2010 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit:


View Full Document

MIT 14 123 - Attitudes Towards Risk

Download Attitudes Towards Risk
Our administrator received your request to download this document. We will send you the file to your email shortly.
Loading Unlocking...
Login

Join to view Attitudes Towards Risk and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or
We will never post anything without your permission.
Don't have an account?
Sign Up

Join to view Attitudes Towards Risk 2 2 and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or

By creating an account you agree to our Privacy Policy and Terms Of Use

Already a member?