DOC PREVIEW
MIT 24 221 - Study Notes

This preview shows page 1 out of 2 pages.

Save
View full document
View full document
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 2 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience
Premium Document
Do you want full access? Go Premium and unlock all 2 pages.
Access to all documents
Download any document
Ad free experience

Unformatted text preview:

24.211 Metaphysics October 20, 2005 There is life on earth. There is life on earth or there isn’t. All planets are under 106 miles in diameter. All planets are over 10-6 in diameter. There are nine planets in the solar system. There are planets in the solar system.true as it happens – contingently true true but not as it happens – necessarily true There are several notions of necessity that could be driving our intuitions here. Truths of logic andmathematics are necessary in every sense. Likewise conceptual truths like “Nothing is bigger than itself.”Other truths are necessary in a sense, but not the sense we’re interested in. “The volcano will erupt” – necessary in the sense of guaranteed by initial conditions and laws of nature,but not in our sense, because initial conditions could have been different. (Inevitability) “Salt dissolves in water” – necessary in the stronger sense of guaranteed just by the laws, but notnecessary in our sense, because (it seems) we could have had different natural laws. (Nomic necessity) “I have hands” – necessary in the sense that I am as sure as can be, but not necessary in our sense; thehands could be an illusion. (Certainty) “I exist” – necessary in the sense that I can know it just by the light of reason, with no appeal toexperience, but not necessary in our sense; God may exist necessarily but not me. (A priori) Even if not all a priori truths are necessary, someone might think that necessary truths have to be a prioriknowable. (Why?) Clearly not all necessary truths are known a priori. Take an arithmetical hypothesisthat we haven't yet proved or refuted. Either H is necessary or ~H is. Either way there's a necessary truthwe don't know, and so don't a priori know. But perhaps all necessary truths are knowable a priori? Onepossible counterexample is undecidable arithmetical truths. (Maybe still knowable since a superior beingcould go through the integers one by one.) Kripke rejects this direction too. Examples of necessaryaposteriori truths? So far been talking about de dicto necessity, or necessity as it applies to truths; now we'll look at de re necessity, or necessity as it relates to things and their properties. “Necessarily, all cats are animals”states a de dicto fact about the embedded dictum (all cats are animals). But now here is a de re fact about my cat: it is necessarily a cat, it is impossible for it to lack that property. I have highlighted the distinction syntactically, by putting “necessarily” first in the de dicto sentence andbetween the subject and predicate in the de re sentence. But this is not required: either could have beenwritten either way. The key is in how you read the sentence. So, “All presidents are necessarilyofficeholders” has the "necessarily" in the middle but to the extent we find it true, we're reading it dedicto. “Necessarily, my favorite furball is a cat” has the "necessarily" at the beginning but to the extentwe find it true, we're giving it a de re reading. Often the very same sentence will bear either reading.“Necessarily, the inventor of bifocals invented bifocals,” read de dicto this expresses the truth that there isno way that someone who uniquely invented bifocals to at the same time not invent them. Read de re, itexpresses the falsehood that Benjamin Franklin had to invent bifocals. A lot of people are happy with de dicto modality but have trouble with de re. Why? De re modalityleads naturally to essentialism: the theory that of a thing's properties, some are essential – it couldn't haveexisted without them – and othes are accidental – it could have existed without them. Some find this implausible or even unintelligible. Suppose we say “Socrates is necessarily human.” This is OK because it's naturally read de dicto as attributing necessity to the claim that Socrates is human. If we read it de re however it implies that for some x, x is necessarily human. It's not Socrates so-conceived has to be human. There’s a thing x that however conceived has this property necessarily. That may seemproblematic. Suppose as some people think that x = Socrates = a certain body, or as a certain bunch ofparticles. Conceived as Socrates, x seems essentially human; but conceived as the bunch of particles hedoesn't. Here are three specific objection, variations on a theme. First is from "reductionism." Common to hold that things of one type reduce to or "boil down to" things of another type. So,tables are hunks of matter, people are a kind of animal, and so on. Take numbers are justcertain sets, for instance, 2 = {{}}. The problem is this. Numbers are thought to have theirarithmetical properties, e.g., primeness, essentially. But the same is not true of sets; it makes nosense to say a set is essentially prime. Yet by Leibniz's Law, identicals have the same properties.BUT: it's not really essentialism that leads to these problems, because it makes equally littlesense to say that is set is prime full stop. One response is to say: OK, so numbers are not sets.Another is to say: well "prime" as applied to sets goes via the numbers they are identical to. If agiven set is the number 7, then some sets are prime. Second objection, due to Kneale and Quine, has to do with description-relativity. According tothem, there is no such thing as x being essentially P all by itself, there is only x being P relativeto description D. Here's the trouble you get in if you deny this. (a) 12 = the number of apostles(b) 12 is necessarily composite.(c) The number of apostles is necessarily composite.It's supposed to be obvious that (c) is false. If it's obvious that's because you're reading (c) dedicto rather than de re. The de re reading is: if x = the number of apostles, x is necessarilycomposite. And that seems right. Third objection has a similar spirit. Best to read the whole quote from Quine: perhaps I can evoke the appropriate sense of bewilderment as follows. Mathematicians mayconceivably be said to be necessarily rational and not necessarily two-legged. And cyclistsnecessarily two-legged and not necessarily rational But what of an individual who counts amonghis eccentricities both mathematics and cycling? Is this concrete individual necessary rationaland contingently two-legged or vice vesa? Just insofar as we are talking referentially of theobject, with no special bias towards a background groupingof mathematicians


View Full Document

MIT 24 221 - Study Notes

Download Study Notes
Our administrator received your request to download this document. We will send you the file to your email shortly.
Loading Unlocking...
Login

Join to view Study Notes and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or
We will never post anything without your permission.
Don't have an account?
Sign Up

Join to view Study Notes 2 2 and access 3M+ class-specific study document.

or

By creating an account you agree to our Privacy Policy and Terms Of Use

Already a member?